terça-feira, 18 de fevereiro de 2020

There is only a single subject referent in all the incarnate acts, this personal subject is none other than the eternal Word of God.



Jesus Christ is one divine person who took on human nature. If one says Christ is both a human person and a divine person this is a form of nestorianism. One person and two natures is the correct phraseology. His human nature was created, but he is not a human person. If His hypostasis is called "composite" after the Incarnation that is not because He is now a divine-human Person but because now there is, in His Person, two natures. So, its a composite hypostasis on the level of nature not in the level of hypostasis. The human nature is enhypostatized in Christ's hypostasis.

All Orthodox affirm with Chalcedon a single hypostasis. J.H. accepts no language other than divine-human hypostasis. That there is a composition in the hypostasis of Christ, there is no doubt: He is God and Man, passable and impassive, mortal and immortal, and so on, according to the attributes of both natures. The term "divine-human" - theantropikos, theandrikos - was used, among the Fathers, not in relation to the hypostasis, but in relation to theanthropic energies or activity. 

J.H. later realized the confusion that his statement "[Jesus] is a human person" caused and then tried to clarify his previous post yet he continued to affirm that Christ is a divine-human hypostasis:




Let us take a look at what Fr. John Anthony McGuckin has to say in his book "Saint Cyril of Alexandria and the Christological Controversy":
In the text of the letter there is no direct reference to Constantinople or the Nestorian affair but it is undoubtedly in Cyril's mind for he uses the occasion to affirm the reality of the manhood of Christ but insists on the singleness of his divine personality—the classical and orthodox Alexandrian position from which he will not move an inch in all his subsequent theologising. In the Paschal Homily 17 he takes care to apply the title Meter Theou (a synonym of Theotokos) to demonstrate his point.

J.H.- and those who sided with him - affirmed precisely Nestorius' argument: every nature must be hypostatised:
On the corresponding semantic rules it followed that any real existent had to be hypostatised, and here opened up the real chasm between Cyril's way of thinking and that of Nestorius. The former saw that there could only be one hypostatic reality in Christ, if indeed Christ was to be one (though he meant hypostasis to bear the weight of subject-centre) whereas the latter followed the logical thread more rigidly and argued that every ousia had to be hypostatised separately. [...] Although Cyril would agree that all natures must be hypostatised he did not agree that this meant Christ must therefore have two hypostases. For him the whole point of the argument was that the two natures were not separate independent realities, and thus were both realised, in the one Christ, by one hypostasis. The use of mono-hypostatic language eventually won the day, but it took the next generation, at Chalcedon, to spell the argument out in the technical terms: Two natures (divine and human), one hypostasis (divine) in the one Christ.

Again, the Divine Hypostasis of the Word of God was the single personal subject:
Cyril uses hypostasis largely in the newer sense to describe the manner of the union in Christ. He says frequently, for example, that the union took place `Kath Hypostasin': hypostatically, or on the basis of a hypostatic level. What he means by this is to stress that the union of God and man in Christ is properly understood to have been effected precisely because it was a single individual subject (the hypostasis: God the Word) who realised the union of two different realities (divinity and humanity) by standing as the sole personal subject of both. 

Again, J.H. used the same argument of Nestorius: Christ human nature must have its own hypostasis otherwise its not a real but only notional. 
[Nestorius] studiously avoided using the form hypostasis to describe the christological union, in direct criticism of Cyril's preferred language. When Nestorius did speak of the term it was only to make two points: firstly that the word was highly 'physical' in its associated meanings and utterly inappropriate for use in the christology debate since it could suggest an organic or chemical model of union; and secondly that any ousia without a hypostasis of its own would, therefore, not be a real existent. The latter point was a significant attack on Cyril who had argued that Christ's humanity did not have a corresponding human hypostasis of its own (and thus Christ was not an individual man, rather God the Word enfleshed). Cyril saw this argument as crucial in defending the single subjectivity of the incarnate Lord; Nestorius attacked it on the logico-semantic grounds that if Christ's humanity did not have its own hypostasis then that humanity was only notional, not real. Whereas Nestorius demanded logical exactitude in the theological exchange, Cyril preferred to defend an intuited principle of single subjectivity regardless of the strains his varied use of technical terms placed on his hearers or upon logic itself.  

Now, a excerpt of Fr. John Anthony McGuckin on Nestorius' Christology. Note the resemblance of his Christology and that promoted by J.H:

For Nestorius, the terms Christ, Son or Lord, were thus the correct titles to connote the faith experience of the oneness of the incarnate Saviour. These terms alone were the proper designation of the 'prosopon of union'—that observable phenomenon of the one reality of Christ in whom was also experienced the reality of a single human life (the prosopon of Jesus) and the very presence of the Godhead (the prosopon of the Logos); thus two realities.  
Central to the coherence of Nestorius' thought was his belief that all christological thinking should always begin from this concrete experience the church has of Christ in his double reality. He felt that christology ought never to begin with the man Jesus (which would lead to Adoptionism) or with the divine Logos (which would lead to Docetism or Apollinarism). He complained, for example, that Cyril began the whole doctrinal process from the wrong premise and consequently deduced fallacious results:  
"You start your account with the creator of the natures and not with the prosopon of union. It is not the Logos who has become two-fold, it is the one Lord Jesus Christ who is two-fold in his natures. In him are seen all the characteristics of the divine Logos who has an eternal, impassible, and immortal nature, and all the characteristics of the manhood which is mortal, passible, and created, and lastly those of the union and the incarnation."  
To begin the christological process from any other starting point than the Christ who stands before the eyes of faith as God's unique statement of what the concrete realisation of 'divine' means is, for Nestorius, tantamount to disregarding the whole economy of salvation. But if one starts one's doctrine from Christ, he insists, then the principal lesson learned should be the sense of abiding distinctness in the one Christ's revelation of the divine, and his revelation of the human.  
In so far as a prosopon signifies 'observable aspect' or 'communicable external appearance' then perhaps we can sum up Nestorius' position so far as follows: The eyes of faith recognise in Christ two clearly observed aspects of his reality, which signify to the beholder divinity as well as humanity. Christ, therefore, has two prosopa. At the same time the eyes of faith recognise that this Christ who has two prosopa is not the same as those prosopa themselves. In other words Christ is not the Logos as such. It would be bad theology, for Nestorius, to speak of the pre-existent Christ, since he is not eternal as the Logos is. Nor would it be right to make unqualified statements about the impassibility of Christ since the radical qualification of human limitations and sufferings is an integral part of what the mind understands by the word 'Christ'.  
But in just the same way as the Logos is not synonymous with Christ, neither is the man Jesus of Nazareth. Christ, for Nestorius, was no mere man. The word connotes far more than the term 'the man Jesus'; in fact it connotes the whole mystery of the intimate relationship of this man with the divine Logos, and the union of the Logos with him. Christ is not only a word for the union of these two prosopic realities, it is also the concrete experience, in some way, of how that union has taken place, how it is to be conceived, and how it ought to be articulated by the church. The term Christ signifies the experience of the encounter with this unique composite figure of the Son of God. In the light of this it is not enough merely to insist that there are two prosopa in Christ, because the experience of the unique revelation of Christ calls for the confession that here there is also the `prosopon of union' the one Christ who manifests in a single prosopon (observable reality) the differentiated prosopa of the divine Logos, and the human Jesus. There are two prosopa, and there is one prosopon. This is why the starting point of one's consideration is all-important. If one begins always with the concrete experience of the incarnate Christ, the paradox is solved: the one is revealed as two-fold. The awareness of the double nature, however, is secondary to the experience of the actual oneness of the incarnate Christ, and is only arrived at by deduction from that oneness.
[...]
 Now, a excerpt on St. Cyril's Christology.
This was the natural result of Cyril's theology of hypostatic union-the human nature did not have its own human hypostasis, and was thus not a separate human entity (the man Jesus), simply the human nature of the divine Word; and the Word hypostansed it.
[...]
The nature is, therefore, not conceived as an independently acting dynamic (a distinct human person who self-activates) but as the manner of action of an independent and omnipotent power—that of the Logos; and to the Logos alone can be attributed the authorship of, and responsibility for, all its actions. This last principle is the flagship of Cyril's whole argument. There can only be one creative subject, one personal reality, in the incarnate Lord; and that subject is the divine Logos who has made a human nature his own. Equally, however, the incamated Logos cannot be sensibly understood purely in terms of his own 'proper' divine characteristics (as he would be before the incarnation) since he is now the Logos-acting-in-the-flesh, and in accordance with the conditions of the flesh which he willingly assumed, precisely to make use of those capabilities directly. In other words, for Cyril the Logos did not simply assume a body, as Apollinaris imagined, he assumed a human life and all the relativised conditions that are applicable to that. Cyril constantly reminds his readers that in christology one must not speak of the Logos as `Gymnos' (ie. naked, in his divine characteristics) but as `Sesarkomene' (enfleshed). The subject is unchanged, the divine Logos, but that subject now expresses the characteristics of his divinely powerful condition in and through the medium of a passible and fragile condition. Cyril, by preference calls this economy a Kenosis or self emptying, following the terms of Philippians 2.6-11, a central text in the debate.
[...]
In the first place [St. Cyril] holds fast to the primary proposition that there is only a single subject referent in all the incarnate acts, in all the psychic and intellectual life of the incarnate Lord, and that this personal subject is none other than the eternal Word of God. For him, this primary principle had to be defended against the very suspicion of any compromise, and he did so throughout his life however many paradoxes necessarily had to be invoked to keep it intact. This determined focus explains all his theological motivation. 
Excerpt From Byzantine Theology by John Meyendorff:
In Christ, the union of the two natures is hypostatic: they "concur into one person [prosopon] and one hypostasis," according to the Fathers of Chalcedon. The controversies which arose from the Chalcedonian formula led to further definitions of the meaning of the term hypostasis. While Chalcedon had insisted that Christ was indeed one in His personal identity, it did not clearly specify that the term hypostasis, used to designate this identity, also designated the hypostasis of the pre-existing Logos. The anti-Chalcedonian opposition in the East so built its entire argument around this point that Byzantine Christology of the age of Justinian committed itself very strongly to excluding that interpretation of Chalcedon which would have considered the "prosopon, or hypostasis," mentioned in the definition as simply the "prosopon of union" of the old Antiochian School., the new synthetic reality resulting from the union of the two natures. It affirmed, on the contrary, following Cyril of Alexandria, that Christ's unique hypostasis is the pre-existing hypostasis of the Logos; that is, that the term is used in Christology with exactly the same meaning as in the Trinitarian theology of the Cappadocian Fathers: one of the three eternal hypostases of the Trinity "took flesh," while remaining essentially the same in its divinity. The hypostasis of Christ, therefore, pre-existed in its divinity, but it acquired humanity by the Virgin Mary.


sexta-feira, 14 de fevereiro de 2020

Maximus Confessor: precursor of Thomas Aquinas or of Gregory Palamas?

I. The Ontological Aspect: The Objects of Free Choice in the Eschaton and Their Properties

A. In contradistinction to Plotinus and Origen, there is no ontological identity and mutual equivalence of the categories of Essence, Will, and Energy. Rather, St. Maximus distinguishes three categories. These are Person, Energy, and Essence. These categories are not mere conventions of speech for St. Maximus, but rather correspond to distinct metaphysical realities. They are not therefore each names for the same, absolutely simple "Something." Thus, while God is simple, this simplicity is not to be understood along the lines of the definitional model of simplicity, where the term functions as a great metaphysical "equals" (=) sign. There is in God a real plurality, different kinds of eternity and infinity. In particular, the One Logos is many logoi, and these logoi are in fact divine energies, each eternal, each infinite, each fully and equally good and divine, each distinct from any other, and yet each in no way divided or separated from each other. Logically speaking, this is an extension of the principle of Cyrillic Chalcedonianism, where the christological terms of the Chalcedonian definition may be used in confessions of triadology, and vice-versa. Thus, while the adjectives "unconfused" and "unseparated" were originally used of the relations between deity and humanity in Christ, they may also be used to describe the relationship of the logoi, or divine energies, both to each other and to the One Logos.[3] With such distinctions between the essence of God and its energies, as well as the distinctions between the energies themselves, there is a resulting plurality of real, yet not opposed, Goods in God. God is consequently left free to create or not to create, for the Neoplatonic and Origenist Problematics and the identification of Essence and Activity, of diversity and opposition, that they embody are completely avoided.

B. This consideration leads inevitably to the crucial interpretive problem involved in any study of St. Maximus. Is the Confessor to be seen as the precursor of Thomas Aquinas, or of Gregory Palamas? It is therefore necessary to say something at this point about this subject, taking Fr. Juan Miguel Guarrigues' article "L'energie divin et la grace chez Maximo le Confesseur" in Istina 19 (1974) as the point of departure for our remarks, for the current study bears some relationship to the conclusions that Fr. Garrigues there presents.

In the main, this article must be seen less as an attack on Palamism and more as a subtle attempt to portray the Confessor as an incipient Thomist. In the opening remarks of the article, Fr. Garrigues endeavors to place the Palamite interpretation of the decisions of the Sixth Ecumenical Council in a bad light by somewhat confusing terminological acrobatics regarding the words "has" and "is":
The Sixth Ecumenical Council has quite thoroughly confessed that the divine nature and the human nature have the energies which are their own properties. But it is nowhere insinuated that the energy which the divine nature has might be really or formally distinct from the essence which it is. [4]
Thus far, Fr. Garrigues' remarks are true and logical enough. It is, however, when he presses his case on "having" and "being" that he runs into trouble, for too much is proved by such an approach:
If, on the contrary, the energy is the energy proper to its essential form, whatever is said of the energy formally characterizes the essence of which it is the energy.... The divine essence does not have an energy, it is energetic, that is to say, that it actualizes all the virtualities of its being.5
This is because "Maximus views the energy as a power of essential existence" [6] Consequently
the essence is not able to have any other proper attributes or energies other than those which it is. For the energy ontologically presupposes the essence in which it inheres.[7]
But even though the argument thus far has been reasonable enough, it is precisely at this point that it begins to break down:
In God the essence does not support the trinity of persons. They have the divine essence. Because they enhypostatize the essence, they are God, but, as persons, they are not implied that the divine essence as it implies its own natural energy.... In effect, only a person of the Trinity is able to have in addition to His own divine being and operation, a human being and operation. The essence is operative, the persons have the operations. [8] 
The argument seems powerful, but, unfortunately, it simply does not fit St. Maximus, who evidently does not observe such rigid rules concerning "having" and "being," for he can write "the One Logos is many logoi, and the many logoi are one (πολλοί λόγοι ὁ εἷς λόγος ἐστί, καί εἷς οἱ πολλοί)." [9] These logoi are also energies, [10] which Fr. Garrigues would view more in the sense of attributes, or alternative names of God; God has what He is and is what He has. But one could, on Fr. Garrigues' approach, maintain that the One logos is no different than the Wisdom, Justice, and Omnipotence which it has. Since St. Maximus quite clearly uses the verb "is" to describe the relationship between the Logos and its logoi, Fr. Garrigues' argument leads to one of two conclusions:, either the logoi are many enhypostasizations of the One Logos, or the One Logos is itself, by an attribute, being composed of many other attributes. Are the logoi persons? Or is the Logos an attribute?

Fr. Garrigues' next argument is crafted with much more care. The whole thrust, and thereby the whole problem, of Palamism is, according to Fr. Garrigues, not in the affirmation that the divine energies are confessed to be uncreated, but that they are in fact said to be in a real manner ontologically distinct from the divine essence, and he even calls in Patriarch Nikephoros I of Constantinople (806-815) as support for the opposing view:
in presenting itself in the line of the council of 680, the Palamite council of 1351... had reason to wish to say that the fathers of the 6th Ecumenical Council have affirmed that the uncreated divine essence implies an uncreated energy in Christ. It is wrong, however, to claim from the Palamite council that it thought that the 6th Council wished to confess a real or formal distinction between the divine essence and its energies, whereas its whole argument against the theandric energy of Monenergism rests on the contrary postulate.... Nikephoros of Constantinople repeats the argument of St. Maximus and the 6th Council which declared that the energy is inherent to the nature: `There is neither essence without energy nor energy without essence' (PG 100:304D). Then, making explicit the postulate which subtends christological dyoenergism, he recalls that, in God, the energy is only able to be distinguished from the essence by reason of its created effects....' It is orthodox to regard the divine energy as eternal, or, to speak more correctly, to regard the energy of God Himself (αυτενέργεια) on account of the impossibility of distinguishing the energy from the essence, for they fall under the same essential principle on account of the property of the simple and incorruptible nature from which they proceed....[11]
This leads Fr. Garrigues to the suggestion that Palamas himself desired less to confess a real distinction between essence and energies and more to preserve one of the most fundamental tenets of the Christian faith, that man may participate in God's divine life.[12] Nevertheless, this real distinction between God's essence and His energies is, Fr. Garrigues maintains, a "sort of eternal emanation of grace logically anterior and independent" of Christ's acts as Creator and Redeemer, [13] for such a distinction is "a reduction of the idea of participation to entitative participation," a distinctly "neoplatonic conception" which "ignores two other modes of participation: participation in the causality of the act of being and intentional participation proper to spiritual beings."[14] Thus we arrive at the real center and root of Fr. Garrigues' difficulties with Palamism: its alleged Neoplatonism.

Palamas' mistake is, according to Fr. Garrigues, that he has no conception of God's essence as "pure aseity." That is to say,
In the manner of the Neoplatonic One, the divine essence is not situated originally in the simplicity of Being in Its pure act, but in that which is Beyond-Being, separated and radically imparticipable. [15]
Consequently, in order to safeguard the doctrine of a real communion between God and the World, Palamas "has to posit a real distinction between the divine essence and its uncreated acts in which creatures participate."[16] And here, very suggestively, Fr. Garrigues brings in the name of Eunomios: 
The god of Eunomios is the infinitely unique monad, radically separate in his essence, and does not admit of any participation in his being... [17] 
The Son cannot, therefore, along Eunomios' model, be fully God by essence, but only by participation in God's energies. 
And viola! For the first time, with the determination of the essence as pure aseity, the distinction between imparticipatable essence and participatable energies is posited.[18] 
According to Fr. Garrigues, then, Palamas, being unable to see God's essence in terms of a "pure aseity" where simple being exists in its pure act, not only "having" that pure act but "being" it as well, [19] must go on to posit some formal distinction between essence and energies. And this, "notwithstanding all precautions, necessarily implies distinction and composition in God." [20] And this in turn leads to the hub of Fr. Garrigues' concern over Palamism, for this distinction "ruins the simplicity of His essence."[21] 

These points are crucial, for, as Chapter Two of this essay has demonstrated, while Plotinus certainly wished to affirm the One's absolute transcendence, his somewhat "definitional" model of simplicity led to precisely that identification of being and activity that Fr. Garrigues would have us embrace, and this identification led in turn to the Origenist Problematic, whose solution was to affirm the precise distinction he would have us deny. 

The implications of this particular aspect of St. Maximus' doctrine of free choice are immense, for the Confessor's doctrine is simply not conceivable, possible, or compatible, with the doctrine of simplicity that Fr. Garrigues is advocating. Lars Thunberg is even more to the point: 
The logos is, as we have underlined, Himself and many logoi, but then the logoi may be said to be the one and only Logos, although what we know of them and their variety does not exhaust what is contained in the Logos. There is no complete identity. As differentiated, the logoi never cease to be different from one another.... The logoi are thus not identical with the essence of God, nor with the empirical forms of existence of the things of the created world.[22]
C. In contradistinction to Plotinus, where the category of things "around God" or "around the One" serves to distinguish the second and third hypostases from the One, where the latter is stable and immutable and the former move "around" it, and in contradiction to Origen where this preposition denotes a category of preexistent souls which are "around" God, in Maximus it serves to signify those energies which are in and "around" a nature. Here "around" serves to designate the fact that the energies "around" an essence are of an infinite "extension" and therefore do not exhaustively define the contents of their essence, and thus are not metaphysically identical with that essence.[23] 

D. In a lengthy footnote (note 49) at the bottom of page 95 of his classic study of St. Maximus, Polycarp Sherwood had this to say about this category of things "around" God: 
I would not only ask, have we here a distinction so developed that it might serve as a later ground for the doctrine of uncreated energies? [24]
The answer to this question in the light of the current study must be an unequivocal "yes." In this regard, the manner of translating περι is of some importance and is indicative of a translator's biases. Sherwood himself should perhaps have been a little more literal in his translation of περι, for he hesitates to give it its full force in English as "around" and prefers the more enervated "about." 

Such a class or category of things is, as we have seen, evident already in Plotinus, and persists into St. Gregory of Nazianzus, who can speak of "things around Him" (τὰ περι αυτόν) from which we may infer "the things proper to Him" (τὰ κατ' αύτόν).[25] Not surprisingly, Fr. Garrigues unhesitatingly translates περι αυτόν not as "around," a translation that he suggests is "trifling,"[26] but as "concerning the subject of God." This seems unjustified, for if the fathers are often alleged to be, at least in terminology if not in intent and content, Neoplatonists, then it would seem more reasonable to give the preposition περι the full sense that it has in Neoplatonism as "around." 


From the book "Free choice in Saint Maximus the Confessor" by Joseph P. Farrell (pages 178-185)

Notes


3. St. Maximus, TheoPol 1, PG91:20B: Ambigua 7. PG91: 1069B. cf. 1077C-1081C; Ambigua 22. PG 91:1257AB: Gnostic Centuries. PG 90:1101B. 11019, 1096D: Alain Riou, Le Monde et L'Eglise. p. 59: Lars Thunberg. Man and the Cosmos, pp.138-139, 140-193.
4. Garrigues, "L'énergie", p. 272, author's emphasis.
5. Ibid., author's emphasis.
6. Ibid., p. 273, citing TheoPol 16, PG91:205B and I Ambig 2. PG 91:1037C.
7. Ibid., author's emphasis, citing TheoPol 1, PG 91:33B, p. 273.
8. Ibid. The underlined portions are the author's emphasis, the italicized portions my own.
9. Ambigua 7, PG91:1081C.
10. Ambigua 22, PG 91:1257AB, cf. Riou, Le Monde, pp. 59-60.
11. Garrigues, "L'energie", p. 273, Fr. Garrigues'  emphasis.
12. Ibid., pp. 274-275.
13. Ibid., p. 275.
14. Ibid., pp. 275-276, Fr. Garrigues' emphasis.
15. Ibid., p. 275.
16. Ibid. 
17. Ibid., p. 277. 
18. Ibid. 
19. Ibid., p. 275. 
20. Ibid., p.279. 
21. Ibid., p.280, emphasis mine. 
22. Thunberg, Man and the Cosmos, p. 139, emphasis mine.
23. TheoPol 16, PG 91:209A, TheoPol 17, PG 91:212D; TheoPol 23, PG 91:261AB;Ambigua 15,PG91:1220D. 
24. Polycarp Sherwood, The Earlier Ambigua of St. Maximus the Confessor and His Refutation of Origenisin, p. 95, note 49. 
25. St. Gregory of Nazianzus, Fourth Theological Oration (Oration 30): 17, PG 31:125BC: 
26. Garrigues,"L'energie",p. 281.