From Volume 2 of An Introduction to Nineteenth Century Russian Slavophilism: A Study in Ideas, translator: Peter K. Christoff; revised, TRV
Not so long ago, the predilection for philosophy held
sway in Europe. Even political questions were of secondary importance,
subordinated to solutions of philosophical systems, borrowing from them
their ultimate meaning and inner significance. But lately, the interest
in philosophy has perceptibly diminished, and, since 1848, the
relationship between philosophy and politics has completely changed.
Now, political questions engage the attention of thinking people;
philosophical works have almost ceased to appear; few are concerned with
philosophical systems any more, and justifiably so. There is no room
for abstract, systematic thinking within the narrow confines of today’s
tremendous social developments, developments pervaded with universal
significance and that follow sequentially with the speed of theatre
sets.
Moreover, the philosophical development of Western
Europe has reached such a degree of maturity that the appearance of a
new system no longer agitates people’s minds as vigorously and as
obviously as before; it no longer staggers people with the contrast
between new conclusions and old concepts. The philosophical orientation
towards autonomous rational thought which began in the West about the
time of the Protestant Revolution, and whose first representatives in
philosophy were Bacon and Descartes, has steadily grown and spread in
the course of three and one-half centuries, sometimes proliferating into
numerous separate systems, sometimes combining to produce their great
summations, thus passing through all the stages of possible progress,
and has finally attained the last, all-inclusive conclusion beyond which
European man’s mind cannot aspire without completely changing its basic
orientation. For when man rejects every authority except his abstract
thinking, can he advance beyond the view which presents the whole
existence of the world as the transparent dialectic of human reason, and
human reason as the self-consciousness of universal being? Obviously,
in this case, the ultimate goal which can be conceived by abstract
reasoning separated from other cognitive faculties, is the goal he has
been approaching for centuries, has now attained, and beyond which is
nothing further to seek.
Lacking opportunity to move forward, philosophy can only
expand in breadth, developing details and giving all individual
disciplines a common basis. Therefore, we see that almost all
contemporary Western thinkers, however they may differ amongst
themselves, proceed from the same level of basic principles. Hegel’s
followers speak in a more pedantic language; those who have not read him
use a more everyday language; but almost all, even those who have not
heard his name, express the principal conviction which is the basis and
the final conclusion of Hegel’s system. This conviction is, so to speak,
in the air of contemporary culture. Even though few works are published
on philosophy, there is little debate on philosophical questions, and
interest in philosophical systems has waned, we should not conclude
interest in philosophical thought itself has diminished. On the
contrary, more than ever it has penetrated all other spheres of reason.
Every phenomenon in social life, every discovery of science, transcends
in the mind the boundaries of its apparent sphere, and, joined to
universal human problems, assumes rational-philosophical significance.
The very universal nature of social developments contributes to this
turn of mind. Interest in academic system-building is dead; however,
greater are the efforts by which every educated person seeks to draw the
guiding strand of his abstract thought through all the labyrinths of
social life, through all the marvels of new scientific and scholarly
discoveries, and through the infinite variety of their possible
consequences. New philosophical systems are no longer appearing, but the
supremacy of rationalism continues.
This rational thought, which received its final
consciousness and expression in modern German philosophy, combines all
phenomena of contemporary European culture into a single common
character. Life’s every movement is permeated by the same spirit and
every intellectual phenomenon prompts the same philosophical
convictions. The discrepancies between these rational-philosophical
convictions and the tenets of faith have caused several Western
Christians to attempt opposing them with philosophical views based on
faith. The most brilliant efforts of Western Christian thinkers have
served only as additional proof of the lasting supremacy of rationalism.
For the opponents of philosophy, in their efforts to refute its
conclusions, are unable to detach themselves from the foundation from
which philosophy naturally developed, and from which no other results
could be obtained, without doing violence to that foundation. Thus, many
pious men in the West, staggered by the irresistible tendency of
thought towards unbelief, and wishing to rescue faith, completely reject
all philosophy as something incompatible with religion, and condemn
reason in general as something contrary to faith. But these pious men in
the West fail to note that by persecuting reason they do even greater
harm to religious convictions than the philosophers themselves. For what
kind of religion is it that cannot stand in the light of science and
consciousness? What kind of faith is it that is incompatible with
reason?
Thus, it appears a believer in the West has almost no
means of rescuing faith except by preserving its blindness, and by
timidly guarding it against contact with reason. This is an unfortunate —
but unavoidable — consequence of the inner dichotomy of faith itself.
For whenever the teaching of faith deviates even a little from its basic
purity, the deviation, growing little by little, cannot help becoming a
contradiction to faith. The lack of wholeness and inner unity of faith
compels one to seek unity in abstract thinking; and reason, having
received equal rights with Divine Revelation, first serves as the ground
of religion, and subsequently replaces it.
When I speak of the division within faith and of the
abstract-rational basis of religion, I refer not only to the Protestant
confessions, where the authority of tradition has been replaced by the
authority of individual understanding. We see abstract reason as the
very foundation of religious doctrine in the Latin confession no less
than in Protestantism, despite that, in its struggle with Protestantism,
the Latin confession denied rationalism solely on the basis of
tradition. For it was only in its opposition to Protestantism that the
Latin confession placed its tradition above human reason. However, on
matters of faith in relation to the Church Universal, Old Rome gave
preference to abstract syllogism over Holy Tradition, which is the
repository of the common consciousness of the whole Christian world and
holds it together in a living, indissoluble unity. Actually, this
preference for syllogism over tradition was the only condition for the
separate and independent rise of Old Rome. For how else could the Latin
confession have become divorced from the Church Universal? It defected
from it only because it wished to introduce new dogmas into the faith,
dogmas unknown to Holy Tradition, born of arbitrary deductions of the
logic of Western peoples. From this root comes the initial division in
the very basic principle of Western religious doctrine, from which first
developed Scholastic philosophy within faith, then the Reformation in
faith, and finally, philosophy outside faith. The Scholastics were the
first rationalists; their progeny are called Hegelians.
However, the orientation of Western philosophies
differed according to the various religious confessions from which they
arose; for every particular confession inevitably assumes a special
attitude of reason towards faith which determines the particular
character of the thought from which it derives.
The Latin confession separated from the Church Universal
as a consequence of a deduction of formal-logical reason which sought a
superficial connection of concepts and derived from it its conclusions
about their essence. It was only such superficial reason, only this
placing of syllogisms above the living consciousness of all Christendom,
that could wrest Old Rome from the Church. Having deprived itself of
the support of Holy Tradition and the common, unanimous sympathy of the
Church, the Latins were compelled to seek support in some sort of
theological system. But, since human reason — particularly the
rationalistic type — may comprehend the Divine variously, according to
each individual’s conceptions, and since the contradictions in
theological arguments could no longer be resolved through the inner
agreement of the whole Church — visible and invisible, the Church of all
ages and all peoples — the unanimity of thought of the Western
Christians had to be safeguarded by the external authority of the
hierarchy. Thus, external authority, independent of any inner authority,
became the ultimate basis of faith. Thus, the relationship between
faith and reason assumed a character where reason had to submit blindly
to religious doctrine affirmed by the external authority of the
hierarchy. I say blindly, because no inner cause could be sought for a
given theological opinion when the truth or falsity of opinion was
determined by the arbitrary opinion of the hierarchy. Hence, we had
Scholasticism, with all its speculative refinements, which sought
endlessly to reconcile the demands of reason with declarations of the
hierarchy, and in so doing consistently drifted from the demands of
reason into a countless multitude of heretical systems and
interpretations.
Meanwhile, leaving the ultimate decision concerning
Divine truths to the reason of the hierarchy which acted without
reference to tradition and the Church Universal, the Latins had to
recognise its hierarchy as the source of all truth, and to subject the
whole realm of human thought and the whole development of the mind in
the field of science and social life to the verdict of the hierarchy.
For everything is concerned to a greater or lesser degree with questions
of Divine truth, and once the reason of the hierarchy transgressed the
boundaries of Divine Revelation, what was to stop it? The example of
Galileo is no exception; it expresses the constant law of the general
relationship of the Western confessions to human thought. Therefore, the
Protestant Revolution was necessary for reason to be rescued from
complete blindness or complete absence of faith; it had to grow out of
the same principle from which the Latins derived their right to reason’s
uniqueness and universal interference. The only difference was this:
the right of judgment over Divine Revelation, preserved in the [Western]
tradition, was transferred from the reasoning of a temporary hierarchy
to the reasoning of all Protestants. Instead of a single external
authority equally binding on all, each individual’s conviction became
the basis of faith.
This constituted the other extreme of the same deviation
from truth. The boundaries between man’s natural reason and Divine
Revelation were equally violated by the Latin and Protestant
confessions, only in a different manner; thus their respective attitudes
towards culture were different. In the former, the basis of faith was
tradition subjected to the sole judgment of the hierarchy, which
controlled the general development of reason with its arbitrary opinions
and endeavoured to compel all thinking into a single arbitrary form. In
the latter, all that was left of the tradition was the letter of the
Scriptures, whose meaning depended on each individual’s understanding.
These two attitudes were bound to give birth to two
entirely opposite intellectual orientations. Under the influence of the
Latin confession, the mind had willy-nilly to reduce all its knowledge
to one system. The main truth was given, the manner in which it was
interpreted was determined, and many features of its relationship to
reason were indicated; it remained only to bring the whole system of
thought into agreement with the given concepts and to remove from reason
everything which might contradict them. In contrast, Protestantism,
besides the letter of the Scriptures, had for the guidance of the mind
only the individual opinions of the reformers; opinions irreconcilable
in their most essential principles: the basic relationship of man to
God, the relationship of free will to grace and predestination, and
other, similar rational attitudes of faith, were understood by the
reformers in an entirely different way from the start. Thus human reason
had to seek a common basis of truth outside the traditions of faith —
within each individual’s thinking. It was thus necessary that rational
philosophy should come into existence: not to develop existing truth
further, not to become imbued with it, not to rise to its level, but
above all to find it. Besides, not having a single and firm foundation
for truth in faith, could man fail to appeal to thought abstracted from
faith? The very love of Divine truth compelled him to seek a rational
philosophy. If rational philosophy, developing outside Divine
Revelation, enticed man into unbelief, the initial blame for this
misfortune lies, of course, not with Protestantism but with the Latins,
who, having the truth and being a living part of the living Church,
deliberately broke away from it.
More concerned with superficial unity and outward
dominion over minds than with inner truth, Old Rome preserved the
monopoly of interpretation for its hierarchy; it could not act otherwise
if it were to avoid dividing into a multitude of contradictory
doctrines. The people were not supposed to think, nor understand the
liturgy, nor read Holy Scripture. They could only listen without
understanding and obey without questioning. They were considered an
unconscious mass upon which rested the edifice of the Latin confession
and had to remain unconscious in order for it to remain standing.
Therefore, almost all independent thought originating sincerely and
naturally within the Latin confession necessarily turned into opposition
to it, which in turn rejected and persecuted almost all outstanding
thinkers. Every stirring of the mind not in accord with the hierarchy’s
arbitrary concepts was heresy, for its concepts, stamped with the
hierarchy’s authority, officially penetrated all the spheres of reason
and life.
In contrast, the Protestant Revolution was instrumental
in the development of the intellectual culture of the peoples it rescued
from the intellectual oppression of Old Rome, the most intolerable of
all oppressions. This constitutes its chief merit: it restored to man
his dignity and won for him the right to be a rational being.
Nevertheless, there was no strength in this rationalism to steadily
sustain it above the natural commonplace level. Torn away from
sympathetic relations with the True Church, screened from such relations
by Old Rome, the Protestant peoples saw nothing divine around them but
the letter of the Scripture and their inner conviction. And, in their
joy at being liberated from intellectual bondage, they overlooked the
truth in the deified letter of the Scripture: that God not only brought
to earth a teaching, but also established a Church to which He promised
uninterrupted existence to the end of time; that He established His
teaching within His Church, not outside it. Protestants saw nothing save
falsehoods and errors between their time and the early Christian
centuries. They thought that, despite the promises of the Saviour, the
gates of hell had vanquished the Church, that the Divine Church was
already dying, and that it was left to them to resurrect it upon the
foundation of the Holy Scripture. However, the Holy Scripture, receiving
no unanimous interpretation, acquired different meaning according to
each individual’s views. Therefore, in order to find a common basis of
truth not only in man’s reason in general, but necessarily in that part
of reason accessible to every individual, Protestant-inspired
philosophy had to limit itself mainly to the sphere of logical
[dianoetic] reason, of which every person was equally capable regardless
of his inner capacity and constitution. The coordination of all
cognitive faculties into a single force, the inner wholeness of the mind
essential for the comprehension of the whole truth — this could not be
within everyone’s reach. Only reason — relative, negative, logical
[dianoetic] reason — could be considered a general authority; it alone
could demand from each individual the absolute acceptance of its
deductions.
Therefore, we observe that rational philosophy developed
almost exclusively in Protestant countries. For what is called French
philosophy is, strictly speaking, English philosophy transferred to
France when faith was in decline. Although Descartes was French, and
though in mid-seventeenth century France almost all thinking people
adhered to his system, by the beginning of the eighteenth century it had
spontaneously ceased to be the commonly accepted view, so little did it
conform to the special nature of the people’s thought. The change which
Malebranche wished to make in it had even less stability. Meanwhile,
for German thought, Descartes became the fountainhead of all philosophy.
France might have produced its own positive philosophy
if Bossuet’s Gallicism had not been limited to diplomatic formality, but
had developed more fully, more consciously, with greater inner freedom,
and had freed cultured Frenchmen from Old Rome’s intellectual
oppression before they lost their faith. The elements of this possible
French philosophy were contained in what was common to the convictions
of the Port-Royal school and the special opinions of Fénelon. For
besides dissimilarities to the official concepts of Old Rome, a feature
common to both was that they strove to develop the inner life in its
depth and sought the living bond between faith and reason beyond the
sphere of external linking of concepts. Port-Royal and Fénelon received
this orientation from the same source, from that part of Christian
philosophy they found in the ancient Church Fathers and was not included
in Old Rome’s teaching.
Pascal’s thoughts could have been a fruitful embryo for this philosophy new to the West. His unfinished work [the Pensées]
not only revealed new grounds for the understanding of the moral order
of the world, for the comprehension of the vital relationship between
Divine Providence and human freedom, but also contained profound
suggestions in the direction of a different manner of thinking,
differing equally from Latin Scholasticism and rational philosophy. If
the sparks of his ideas had united in the common consciousness with
those which inspired Fénelon — when, in defence of Guyon, he collected
the teachings of the Church Fathers on the inner life — then from the
combined flame there would surely have arisen a new, original philosophy
which might have saved France from unbelief and its consequences. Of
course, such a philosophy would not have been pure truth, since it would
have remained outside the Church, but it would have come closer than
any rational speculation. However, the machinations of the Jesuits
destroyed Port-Royal and its group of recluse-thinkers. With them also
perished the nascent, life-giving orientation of their thought. The
cold, solemn logic of Bossuet failed to grasp what was vibrant and warm
in Fénelon’s deviation from the official thought of Old Rome, and with
self-satisfaction [Bossuet] invoked papal authority to compel him
[Fénelon] to renounce his cherished convictions out of respect for papal
infallibility. In this manner, France’s indigenous philosophy was
stillborn, and educated French society, demanding some sort of
intellectual relaxation, had to submit to Voltaire’s raucous laughter
and to the laws of an alien philosophy, which was all the more hostile
to French religious convictions for having nothing in common with them.
In England, Locke’s system could still be somewhat reconciled with
faith, under which it grew up; but in France, it assumed a destructive
character and, passing from Condillac to Helvetius, destroyed the last
vestiges of faith by its dissemination.
Thus, among those nations whose intellectual life was
subject to the papacy, an indigenous philosophy was impossible. But,
meantime, the growth of learning demanded thinking capable of
comprehending and assimilating it. Between the thriving science of the
world and the formal faith of Old Rome, lay a chasm the thinking Latin
had to cross with a leap of desperation. Human reason could not always
manage this leap, nor was it always in agreement with the conscience of
the sincere Christian. Hence, rationalistic philosophy, born in
Protestant countries, spread to Latin lands as well, permeating all
European culture with one common character, and replacing the former
unanimity of faith of the Western nations with the unanimity of abstract
reason.
But man’s thought did not arrive at its final conclusion
all at once. Only gradually did it cast aside all irrelevant data,
finding them insufficiently reliable for the basic affirmation of the
original truth. Initially, its activity split in two directions. Among
Romance nations, which by their historical character strove to combine
inner self-consciousness with external life, arose an empirical or
sensuous philosophy, starting with separate observations and moving to
general conclusions, deducing all the laws of being and thinking from
the order of external nature. Among Germanic nations, which as a result
of their historical distinctiveness bore within themselves the constant
sense of the separation of external and inner life, arose the desire to
deduce laws for external being from the very laws of reason. Finally,
both philosophies merged into one intellectual view based on the
identity of reason and being, developing out of this identity the form
of thought which encompassed all other philosophies as separate rungs of
an unfinished ladder leading to the same goal.
However, deriving from the totality of Western European
culture and accommodating the general result of the intellectual life of
Western Europe, contemporary philosophy, like all contemporary European
culture, in its last flowering has been completely severed from its
roots. Its conclusions have nothing in common with its past, towards
which it maintains an attitude not of a culminating, but of a
destructive force. Entirely independent of its past, it now appears as a
new indigenous element and is birthing a new epoch in the intellectual
and social life of the West. It is still very difficult to determine the
true nature of its effect on European culture, for its characteristic
influence is just beginning to be discerned; its ultimate fruits are
concealed in the future.
Moreover, this new system has dominated earlier European
philosophical convictions too briefly to give us the right to think its
fundamental assumptions and its dialectical thought-process are the
exclusive property of our time. In the general life of humanity, recent
philosophy is not as new as is generally assumed. It is new for modern
history, but for human reason in general it is familiar, and hence, the
future consequences of its supremacy over the minds of men have already
been more or less indicated. For the same spirit of thought dominated
the educated world several centuries before the birth of Christ.
Aristotle’s basic views — not those attributed to him by his mediaeval
interpreters, but those which emerge from his works — are identical with
Hegel’s views; and the manner of dialectal thinking which is ordinarily
deemed the exclusive characteristic and particular discovery of Hegel
was, even in the days of Aristotle, the unmistakable attribute of the
Eleatic school. This is so true that, when we read Plato’s Parmenides,
it seems that in the words of the student of Heraclitus we are
listening to the Berlin professor himself, arguing that dialectics is
the chief function of philosophy and its real goal. He sees in it a
miraculous force which transforms every determinate thought into its
antithesis, and from this he produces a new definition. He makes
abstract notions about being, non-being, and becoming the foundation of
the thinking process which embraces all being and knowledge. This is why
the difference between the new and ancient philosophers is neither in
the basic point of view attained by reason, nor in the special manner of
thought discovered by the former, but entirely in the ultimate
completeness of the former’s systematic development and in the wealth of
intellectual acquisitions which man’s curiosity has managed to amass in
the course of his two thousand year search. Now, reason stands on the
same level — not higher — and perceives the same truth, not a more
distant one. Only the contours of the horizon are clearer.
The Western mind seems to have a special kinship with
Aristotle. Appreciation for his thought goes back to the birth of
Western European culture. However, the Scholastics utilised his system
merely as the groundwork for a new truth not directly derived from it,
but taken by them from tradition. When, with the Renaissance,
Aristotle’s unlimited authority declined, it seemed all appreciation of
him would be forever lost. Europe celebrated its liberation from him
with a certain enthusiasm, as a great and redeeming event for the human
mind. Hegel travelled a different road, which stood outside Aristotle’s
system, but nevertheless came to a meeting point with him, both in his
final conclusion and regarding the relationship of the mind to truth. He
constructed another system, but as Aristotle himself would have
constructed it if Aristotle could have been reborn in our time and if,
without changing the level on which human reason stood in his day, he
could simply reduce present-day problems of thought to his point of
view. Hegel’s pupils, replacing Aristotle’s terminology with their own,
recognised in his system the faithful though incomplete reflection of
their teacher’s system. The voice of the modern world echoed the world
of the past.
Classical Greek philosophy originated not directly from
Greek religious beliefs, but under their influence and parallel to them;
it arose from their inner disagreement. The inner disagreement of faith
necessarily led to abstract reasoning. Abstract reasoning and the
tangible and active diversity of the contradictory teachings of faith,
standing in essential opposition to each other, could be reconciled in
the Greek mind only in the contemplation of the beautiful, and perhaps
in the hidden meaning of the mysteries. That is why the Greek sense of
the beautiful stands between the tangibility of Greek mythology and the
abstract reasoning of Greek philosophy. To the Greek, the beautiful was
the focus of all intellectual life. The unfolding of the meaning of the
beautiful, one might say, comprises the whole essence of Greek culture,
both inner and outer. But the limits of its development were contained
in the very nature of the beautiful: the growth of one of its elements
meant the destruction of the other. To the extent that reasoning
developed, mythological faith weakened, and Greek beauty withered with
it. For the beautiful, like the true, disappears in abstraction when it
does not rest on the essential. Rising on the ruins of [mythological]
beliefs, philosophy undermined them and thereby destroyed the creative
wellspring for the development of Greek culture. Philosophy, initially
the expression of Greek culture, at the stage of its full development
became the contradiction of that culture, and though it still bore the
outward signs of mythology, it actually had its own independent
existence. It was born in and grew from Greek concepts, but in its
maturity it became the legacy of mankind as the separate fruit of
reason, maturing, and eventually separating from its natural root.
It may be said that the dominance of pagan beliefs over
human thought came to an end with the last phase of Greek culture, not
because believing pagans were no more, but because advanced culture now
stood outside the limits of pagan faith, transforming mythology into
allegory. Only cultural laggards (who were consequently impotent) could
remain pagan; but as they developed they fell under the dominance of
philosophy.
From this negative view, in the history of mankind,
Greek philosophy appears to have been useful in educating the mind,
freeing it from the false teachings of paganism and, through
intellectual guidance, bringing it to that neutral condition in which it
became capable of accepting a higher truth. Philosophy prepared the
soil for Christian seed.
But, between the time of Aristotle and the general
submission of world culture to Christian teaching, many centuries
elapsed, during which many different and contradictory philosophical
systems nourished, consoled, and disturbed man’s reason. Few of these
systems, however, were characterised by extremes; in general, culture
grew out of what was common to the extremes, out of middle ground.
Between the Stoics’ virtuous pride and the Epicureans’ sensual
philosophy, between the alluring heights of the lofty mental
constructions of the Neoplatonic school and the unfeeling, implacable,
all-uprooting plough of scepticism, stood Aristotle’s philosophy, to
which men’s minds constantly returned from extreme deviations, and which
cast the logical snares of its impartial system into the most biased
forms of thought. This is why it may be said that, whereas in the
ancient pre-Christian world there were several different philosophies
and several mutually contradictory sects, the vast majority of thinking
humanity and all of culture’s moral and intellectual power belonged to
Aristotle. Precisely what influence did Aristotle’s philosophy have on
culture and the moral dignity of man? The solution of the problem is
important, and not only for past history.
It would seem the clearest and briefest answer to this
question may lie in the moral and intellectual mood of the centuries
when this philosophy dominated. The Roman citizen at the time of the
emperors bore the living stamp of its principles. For the ultimate
meaning of any philosophy lies not in individual logical or metaphysical
truths, but in the relationship in which it places man with respect to
the ultimate truth he seeks — in the inner imperative to which the mind
imbued with it turns. Every philosophy in the final stage of its
development produces two results, or, more correctly, a single result
with two aspects: the total product of thought and the preponderant
imperative which derives from this product. The latter truth, which
sustains the mind, points to the treasure which man will seek in science
and in life. At the end of a philosophical system, between its
primordial truth and its cherished goal, is not thought possessing a
specific formula, but only, so to speak, the spirit of the thought, its
inner power, its sacred inner music which accompanies all the stirrings
of the soul of the man convinced by it. This inner spirit, this living
force, is characteristic not only of higher, mature philosophical
systems. A philosophical system belongs in the academic domain, but its
power, its ultimate imperative, concerns the life and culture of all
mankind.
However, one must admit Aristotle’s philosophy, when it
did not serve to support an alien system but acted independently, had a
very lamentable influence on mankind’s culture, an influence in direct
contrast to the influence it exerted on its first student, the great
conqueror of the Orient [Alexander the Great]. The striving for the
better within the limits of the commonplace, for the reasonable in the
everyday sense of the term, for the possible as determined by external
reality, were the final conclusions of the kind of rationality suggested
by Aristotle’s system. There was but one pupil who did not find these
teachings to his liking; all others found them perfectly congenial. It
seems the more Alexander listened to them, the more energetically he
developed his own original ideas antithetical to them — as if in
defiance of his teacher’s counsel. It may even be that without the
stimulus of prudent mediocrity, all the extremism of his imprudent
genius would not have developed. But the remainder of humanity submitted
to the influence of dry and abstract philosophy all the more willingly,
because, in the absence of loftier convictions, the tendency towards
the mundane and prudently commonplace automatically becomes the
predominant characteristic of the moral world.
Aristotle’s system broke the wholeness of man’s
intellectual self-consciousness and transferred the root of man’s inner
convictions from the moral and aesthetic sphere into the abstract
thought of rationality. The means by which it sought to know the truth
were limited to the logical activity of the intellect and to the
detached contemplation of the external world. External existence and the
expressible verbal aspect of thought constituted the only data from
which it derived whatever could be derived by the logical concatenation
of concepts, and one must admit it derived from them all that could be
derived in this manner at the time. In Aristotle’s view, reality was the
complete embodiment of supreme reason. All the discord in the physical
and moral world was only imaginary, and not only was lost in the total
harmony, but actually provided essential tones for its eternally
changing diapason. In his opinion, the world never had been nor ever
would be better. It had always been sufficiently beautiful, for it had
no beginning and would have no end. It would remain eternally whole and
unchanged in its totality, while constantly changing and experiencing
destruction in its parts. But he conceived this integral and satisfying
world in the cold system of abstract unity. He saw the highest good in
thought which comprehends this unity through the diversity of individual
phenomena accompanied by an external life of contentment and
tranquility, i.e., physical and intellectual comfort.
Aristotle said that only when man’s worldly needs are
satisfied can he begin to love wisdom, whereas the Stoics were convinced
that only wisdom can free man from worldly wants and burdens. In
Aristotle’s opinion, virtue does not demand the highest realm of
existence, but consists in finding the golden mean between evil
extremes. Virtue derives from two sources: from the abstract deductions
of the mind (which, being abstract, lend no strength to the spirit and
have no essential compulsory force), and from habit (which is partly the
product of the abstract wish to reconcile will and the dictates of
reason, and partly arises from the accidental nature of external
circumstances).
Obviously, this pattern of thought could produce very
intelligent spectators among human beings, but only extremely
insignificant men of action. In fact, Aristotle’s philosophy had a
destructive effect on man’s moral dignity. By undermining all
convictions which existed above the level of dry and abstract logic, it
destroyed all motivations capable of elevating man above his personal
interests. The spirit of ethics declined and the mainsprings of inner
originality weakened. Man became the obedient tool of surrounding
circumstances, the deliberating but unwilling result of external forces,
intelligent matter obedient to the power of mundane motives: personal
advantage and fear. The few examples of Stoic virtue are rare
exceptions, striking contrasts to the general frame of mind, which
confirm rather than deny the notion of the general absence of inner
independence. For Stoicism could arise only as an intense contrast, a
depressing protest, and a desperate consolation for the few in the face
of the knavery of the many. Nevertheless, even those thinkers who did
not exclusively follow Aristotle, and who only studied his system,
unconsciously introduced the results of his teaching into their
understanding of other philosophers. Thus, Cicero, in the struggle
between the ruin of his fatherland and his own personal safety, sought
justification for his pusillanimity in Plato. However, he only saw in
Plato that meaning in accord with Aristotle. Thus, he consoled himself
with the thought that Plato did not counsel useless resistance to force
and intervention in the affairs of a senile people. Moral insignificance
was generally stamped on everyone, and if, in the time of the Caesars,
with the complete decline of man’s inner dignity, external culture had
been even more highly developed, if there had existed railroads and
electric telegraphs and peksany [a type of artillery], and all
the other discoveries which now subject the world to the authority of
heartless calculation, it is difficult to say what would have become of
poor humanity.
Such was the influence of ancient philosophy, primarily
Aristotelian philosophy, on human nature. There was no salvation for man
on earth. God alone could save him.
However, Christianity, which altered the spirit of the
ancient world and resurrected the lost dignity of man’s nature, did not
unconditionally reject ancient philosophy. For the harm and falsehood of
philosophy lay not in the development of the mind it produced, but in
its final conclusions, which depended on the fact that it considered
itself the highest and only truth, conclusions eliminated as soon as the
noetic faculty recognised a superior truth. In Christianity, philosophy
took a subordinate position, appearing as a relative truth; serving as
the means for the confirmation of the highest principle in the realm of a
different culture.
Although engaged in a life-and-death struggle with the
falsehood of pagan mythology, Christianity did not destroy pagan
philosophy; rather it took it and transformed it in accordance with its
own superior knowledge. The brightest lights of the Church — Justin,
Clement, Origen (insofar as he was Orthodox), Athanasius, Basil,
Gregory, and most of the great Holy Fathers upon whose work, so to
speak, Christian teaching became established in the midst of a pagan
culture — not only were thoroughly versed in ancient philosophy, but
utilised it for the rational construction of the first Christian
gnosiology, which combined the development of science and reason into an
all-embracing vision of faith. The true part of pagan philosophy,
pervaded with the Christian spirit, was the intermediary between faith
and external human culture. Not only while Christianity was still
combating paganism, but in the whole subsequent existence of the East
Roman Empire, we see that thorough study of the Greek philosophers was
the common legacy of almost all Church teachers. For Plato and Aristotle
could only be of use to Christian culture as great scholars; they could
not endanger it as long as Christian truth occupied the summit of
culture. For it should not be forgotten that, in its struggle with
paganism, Christianity did not concede superiority in knowledge to it,
but, permeating paganism, placed in its own service the whole
intellectual activity of the world, past and present, to the extent to
which it was known.
If there was any danger that a Christian people might
deviate from the true teaching, the danger lay primarily in ignorance.
The growth of rational knowledge, certainly, does not offer salvation,
but guards against false knowledge. It is true that where the mind and
heart have once been permeated by Divine truth, there the degree of
learning becomes a side issue. It is also true that consciousness of the
Divine is equally compatible with all stages of rational development.
But, in order that Divine truth might permeate, enliven, and guide man’s
intellectual life, it must subordinate external reason to itself and
dominate it, not remain outside its sphere of action. Divine truth must
stand above other truths in the general consciousness as the sovereign
principle pervading all culture. For each separate Divine truth must be
supported by the like-mindedness of cultivated society. Ignorance, by
contrast, keeps minds from vital intellectual interchange through which
truth among men and nations is sustained, advanced, and enlarged. An
ignorant mind, even when accompanied by the most righteous convictions
of the heart, gives birth to irrational jealousy, from which in turn
springs the deviation of both mind and heart from true convictions.
Such was the case of the West before its defection. The
ignorance of the peoples exposed their intellectual life to the
irresistible influence of the lingering traces of paganism, which
communicated to their thought the rationalistic nature of Old Rome’s
superficial logical abstractness; this deviation of reason in turn
compelled them to seek superficial unity in place of spiritual unity.
Ignorance also enticed them into excessive jealousy of the Arians, so
that, not satisfied with the rejection of the heresy, they created a new
theological dogma of the Godhead [the Filioque] in direct
opposition to the Arians under the influence of this same superficial
logical thought — a dogma they regarded as true only because it was the
direct opposite of one form of heresy, forgetting that the direct
opposite of an error is generally not the truth, but only the other
extreme of the same error. Thus, as a result of the Western peoples’
ignorance, their very striving for church unity divorced them from
unity, and their very striving for orthodoxy caused them to break away
from orthodoxy.
Of course, it was not ignorance alone that
caused the West to separate from the Church. Ignorance is only a
misfortune. Humanity could not be torn from saving truth without moral
guilt. But the possibility and the basis of this guilt lay in ignorance;
without it, even the popes’ love of power could not have succeeded.
Only through the combined action of papal love of power and the
ignorance of the people could the illegal addition to the Symbol of
Faith come to pass; and this initial triumph of rationalism over faith,
together with the unlawful recognition of the supremacy of the popes, is
the permanent obstacle to the return of the West to the Church. But,
having broken away, the Latin confession descended, as though sliding
down a smoothed mountain slope, to all those deviations which
continuously increased its alienation from the truth and produced all
the destructive features of Western culture with all its consequences
for itself — and for us. I say
for us, for the fate of all mankind is in a state of living and sympathetic reciprocity, not always noticeable, but real nevertheless. The defection of Old Rome deprived the West of the purity of Christian teaching, and, meantime, halted the development of culture in the East. What should have been accomplished through the combined efforts of East and West was now beyond the power of the East alone, which was thus condemned only to preservation of Divine truth in its purity and holiness without opportunity to embody it in the external culture of nations.
Who knows? Perhaps this external impotence of the East
was destined to continue until another people, a nation enlightened by
true Christianity, would grow and mature in place of declining Old Rome,
when the West was separating from the East. Perhaps this nation was
destined to arrive at intellectual maturity just when Western
civilisation, by virtue of its own development, would destroy the power
of heterodoxy and would pass from false Christian convictions to
indifferent philosophical convictions, returning the world in due course
to pre-Christian thought. For Christian heterodoxy is less capable of
receiving the truth than a doctrine from which Christian conviction is
entirely absent. In the latter case, there would exist at least the
external possibility of true Christianity gaining supremacy over human
culture. For there is no doubt that all actions and endeavours of
private individuals and nations are subject to the unseen, barely
audible, and often completely imperceptible current of the general moral
order of things, which sweeps before it all general and particular
activity. But this general order of things consists of the concert of
personal wills. There are moments, there are situations, when the state
of things is, so to speak, in balance and a single movement of the will
can determine its direction.
The West faced such a situation at the time of its
defection. For, although popular ignorance weighed heavily upon the
actions of the popes, there is no doubt that the firm and decisive will
of one of them at that time might yet have overcome the error of the
people and might have preserved truth in the West. There was such a
fateful moment, a moment in which the Lord seemed to place the fate of
the whole world in the hands of one person. Had he been firm in the
truth, the world would have been spared centuries of errors and
misfortunes. Peoples would have developed in sympathetic communion of
faith and reason, jointly destroying pagan remnants in the mind of man
and in the life of society. The East would have given the West the light
and strength of intellectual culture, the West would have shared with
the East the development of public life; and everywhere culture would
have been established upon the firm rock of Divine Revelation. The best
spiritual forces would not have been wasted in useless upheavals, with
the new evil of destruction demolishing the old evil of false
construction. The flower of the nations’ manhood would not have perished
from the deadly incursions of alien barbarians or from the unchecked
oppression of internal pagan violence, which continued to triumph over
the culture of the Christian peoples. Social life, developing
harmoniously, would not have destroyed earlier acquisitions with every
new success and would not have sought the ark of salvation in the
mundane calculations of industry or in the starry-eyed construction of
utopias. Universal civilisation does not rest on a dream or on an
opinion, but on truth itself, which affirms it harmoniously and
steadfastly. All this depended on one moment and was perhaps in the
power of one man. But that man did not stand firm, and Western culture,
deprived of sympathy for the Church Universal, was directed towards
earthly goals. The Church in the East, incapacitated by the violence of
still predominant paganism and deprived of the aid of its Western
brethren, took refuge in the monastery.
Incidentally, it appears there was still another moment,
in the sixteenth century, when the Western world could have returned.
The writings of the Holy Fathers, brought from Greece after its fall,
opened the eyes of many Europeans, showing them the difference between
Christian teaching and that of Old Rome. Meanwhile, the abuses of the
Latins reached such tremendous proportions that the peoples became
clearly convinced of the necessity of reforming [what they perceived to
be] the Church. But how to accomplish this reform, no one had yet been
able to decide.
I am now studying the papal decrees, Luther wrote to Melanchthon,
and I find so many contradictions and so much falsehood that it is beyond my power to believe they were inspired by the Holy Spirit, and that we were to base our faith on them. After this, I shall take up the study of the Ecumenical Councils and will see whether the teaching of the Church should not be affirmed upon them in conjunction with the Holy Scripture (certainly bypassing the papal decrees).
If Luther had only remembered that fully one half of the
world calling itself Christian recognised seven Ecumenical Councils,
not sixteen [as did the Latins], and that this half of the Christian
world was innocent of the Latins’ abuses which agitated his soul with
righteous indignation, then perhaps, instead of composing a new
confession according to his personal notions, he might have turned
directly to the Church Universal. He might have still done this, because
the convictions of the Germanic nations had not yet led them to a final
decision, except to hatred of the pope and the desire to escape the
arbitrary rule of Old Rome. All the nations which he had roused would
have followed him, and the West could have again been united with the
Church, especially since the remnants of the Hussite movement were one
of the most important causes of Luther’s success, and the Hussite
movement, as is well known, was imbued with recollections and
reflections of the Orthodox Church [e.g., the Hussites did not use the Filioque
in the Creed]. However, Luther refused to remind himself of the
Orthodox Church, and studied not only the seven Councils, but all those
the Latins called Ecumenical. As a result of this comparison, he wrote
to Melanchthon:
I have been studying the definitions of the Councils. They also contradict each other like the papal decrees. It is obvious we have no choice but to take as the basis of faith the Holy Scripture alone.Thus, the Protestant Revolution was accomplished; its fate decided by a misunderstanding, whether deliberate or unwitting, God alone knows. When, in the seventeenth century, the Protestants addressed to the Eastern patriarchs an enquiry about faith, it was too late. Protestant opinion had already solidified and were aflame with all the heat of new convictions and new, untested hopes.
In mentioning these relations between the beliefs of an
entire people and the accidental nature of the moral arbitrariness of
private individuals, we are not deviating from our subject. On the
contrary, we would obtain a false impression of the development of human
thought if we separated it from the influence of moral and historical
chance. There is nothing easier than to represent every fact of reality
as an inevitable result of supreme laws of rational necessity, but
nothing would so distort the actual understanding of history as these
imaginary laws of rational necessity, which are actually only laws of
rational possibility. Everything must have its own measure and its
proper place. Of course, every moment in the history of mankind is the
direct consequence of the preceding moment and in turn gives birth to
the moment that follows. But one of the elemental forces of these
moments is man’s free will. Failure to recognise this is to deliberately
deceive oneself and substitute the external symmetry of the concept for
the actual knowledge of the living truth.
From these two moments in the life of Western Europe —
when it could have reunited with the Church but did not only because of
the accidental action of human will — we see the culture of Western
Europe, although completely different from Orthodox culture, is,
nevertheless, not quite as far from it as it first appears. In its very
essence lay the necessity of separate periods of development, between
which it was free from preceding influences and therefore was capable of
choosing between orientations.
If, however, at the beginning of the Protestant
Revolution, two solutions were possible, after its full development
there was no longer any way out except the one actually taken.
Constructing the edifice of faith on the personal convictions of the
people is like building a tower according to the notions of each worker.
All that was common to believing Protestants were certain distinctive
beliefs held by their first leaders: the literal reading of Holy
Scripture, and natural reason, upon which the teaching of faith was to
be erected. Today, one would hardly find many Lutheran pastors who would
agree on everything in the Augsburg Confession, although when ordained,
all promise to accept it as the basis of their religious doctrine.
Natural reason, upon which Protestantism was to be affirmed, outgrew the
faith of the people. Philosophical concepts increasingly replaced, and
are still replacing, religious concepts. Passing first through the
period of doubting unbelief, then through the period of fanatical
unbelief, man’s thought finally went over to indifferent unbelief and
together with it to the consciousness of an inner barrenness and the
search for a living conviction, something which would bind man to man,
not by means of cold agreement on abstract convictions, not through
superficial connection of external advantages, but through inner
sympathy of an integral existence pervaded by one love, one reason, and
one aspiration.
But where can the West find these living convictions? To
return to what it formerly believed is impossible. Forced conversions,
artificial faith — these are like the attempts of some lovers of the
theatre to convince themselves that theatre sets are reality itself.
Having shattered the wholeness of the spirit, and having
left the highest awareness of truth to detached logical [dianoetic]
thinking, man lost in the depth of his self-consciousness all
connections with reality, and himself appeared on earth as an abstract
being, as a spectator in the theatre, capable of equal sympathy, love,
and aspiration for all things only on condition that he was free from
anxiety and physical suffering. For the only thing his logical
abstractness did not allow him to do was repudiate his physical being.
Therefore, not only was faith lost in the West, but also poetry, which
in the absence of living convictions became transformed into a barren
amusement; and the more exclusively poetry sought imagined pleasure
alone, the more tedious it became.
Only one serious thing was left to man, and that was
industry. For man, the reality of existence survived only in his
physical person. Industry rules the world without faith or poetry. In
our time, it unites and divides people. It determines one’s fatherland;
it delineates classes; it lies at the base of state structures; it moves
nations; it declares war, makes peace, changes mores, gives direction
to science, and determines the character of culture. Men bow down before
it and erect temples to it. It is the real deity in which people
sincerely believe and to which they submit. Unselfish activity has
become inconceivable. Industry has acquired the same significance in the
contemporary world as chivalry in the time of Cervantes.
Incidentally, we have not yet witnessed everything. One
may say we are seeing only the beginning of the unlimited domination of
industry and of the recent phase of philosophy. Proceeding hand in hand,
they have yet to run the full course of the modern development of
European life. It is hard to see what European culture may come to if
some sort of inner change does not occur among the European peoples. It
is obvious this possible transformation could consist only of a change
in basic convictions, or, in other words, in the change of the spirit
and orientation of philosophy, for this transformation now constitutes
the entire focus of human self-consciousness.
But, as we have seen, the character of the dominant
philosophy depends on the character of the dominant faith. Philosophy
may not derive directly from faith; it may even be in contradiction to
faith; but it is still born of the peculiar orientation of mind given it
by the peculiar character of faith. The same intelligence which enabled
man to understand the Divine also serves him in the understanding of
truth in general.
Under the influence of the Latin confession, this
intellect found expression in logical rationality which, however, acted
only sporadically; it lacked the capacity to create its own unity, for
the wholeness of its activity was destroyed by the intervention of
external authority. Under the influence of the Protestant confessions,
this rationality reached complete development in its separateness and,
conceiving itself supreme in the completeness of its development, called
itself
reason(die Vernuft), in contrast to its former fragmentary activity, to which it left the term
understanding(der Verstand).
But for us, brought up outside the Latin and Protestant
spheres of influence, neither manner of thinking could be completely
satisfactory. Although we submit to Western culture — for we do not yet
have our own — we can submit to it only as long as we are unaware of its
one-sidedness.
In the Church, the relationship between reason and faith
is completely different from their relationship in the Latin and
Protestant confessions. The difference is this: in the Church, Divine
Revelation and human thought are not confused. The boundaries between
the Divine and the human are transgressed neither by science nor by
Church teaching. However much believing reason strives to reconcile
reason and faith, it would never mistake any dogma of Revelation for a
simple conclusion of reason and would never attribute the authority of
revealed dogma to a conclusion of reason. The boundaries stand firm and
inviolable. No patriarch, no synod of bishops, no profound consideration
of the scholar, no authority, no impulse of so-called public opinion at
any time could add a new dogma or alter an existing one, or ascribe to
it the authority of Divine Revelation — representing in this manner the
explanation of man’s reason as the sacred teaching of the Church or
projecting the authority of eternal and steadfast truths of Revelation
into the realm of systematic knowledge subject to development, change,
errors, and the separate conscience of each individual. Every extension
of Church teaching beyond the limits of Holy Tradition leaves the realm
of Church authority and becomes a private opinion — more or less
respectable, but still subject to the verdict of reason. No matter whose
this new opinion might be, if it is not recognised by former ages —
even the opinion of a whole people or of the greater part of all
Christians at a given time — if it attempts to pass for a Church dogma,
by this very claim excludes itself from the Church. For the Church does
not limit its self-consciousness to any particular epoch, however much
this epoch might consider itself more rational than any former. The sum
total of all Christians of all ages, past and present, comprises one
indivisible, eternal, living assembly of the faithful, held together
just as much by the unity of consciousness as through the communion of
prayer.
This inviolability of the limits of Divine Revelation is
an assurance of the purity and firmness of faith in the Church. It
guards its teaching from incorrect reinterpretations of natural reason
on the one hand, and, on the other, guards against illegitimate
intervention by Church authority. Thus, for the Orthodox Christian it
will forever remain equally incomprehensible how it was possible to burn
Galileo [Kireyevsky apparently confused Galileo with Giordano Bruno]
for holding opinions differing from the opinions of the Latin hierarchy,
and how it was possible to reject the credibility of an apostolic
epistle on the ground that the truths it expressed were not in accord
with the notions of some person or some epoch [a reference to Luther’s
rejection of the Epistle of James].
But the more clearly and firmly the limits of Divine
Revelation are defined, stronger is the urgency for believing thought
[noesis] to reconcile the concept of reason with the teaching of faith.
For truth is one, and striving for the consciousness of this unity is
the constant law and the basic stimulus of rational activity.
The more free and more sincere believing reason is in
its natural activities, the more fully and more correctly it aspires
towards Divine truth. For the thinking Orthodox Christian, the teaching
of the Church is not an empty mirror which reflects the features of each
personality; it is not a Procrustean bed which deforms living
personalities according to one arbitrary yardstick; it is rather the
highest ideal towards which believing reason alone can aspire, the
ultimate limit to the highest kind of thought, the guiding star which
burns on high and, reflected in the heart, illumines the path to truth
for reason.
But, in order to bring faith and reason into accord, it
is not enough for the thinking Orthodox Christian to construct rational
concepts in accordance with the tenets of faith, selecting the
appropriate, excluding the offensive, and thus ridding reason of
everything which contradicts faith. If Orthodox thinking consisted of
such a negative approach to faith, the results would have been the same
as in the West. Concepts irreconcilable with faith deriving from the
same source and in the same manner as those compatible with it would
have an equal right to recognition. Thus, the same painful dichotomy
would occur in the very basis of self-consciousness and would sooner or
later unavoidably deflect thought from faith.
But the main difference in Orthodox thinking is
precisely this: it seeks not to arrange separate concepts according to
the demands of faith, but rather to elevate reason itself above its
usual level [move from dianoetic to noetic thinking], thus striving to
elevate the very source of reason, the very manner of rational thinking,
to the level of sympathetic agreement with faith.
The first condition for the elevation of reason is that
man should strive to gather into one indivisible whole all his separate
faculties, which in the ordinary condition of man are in dispersion and
contradiction; that he should not consider his abstract logical
[dianoetic] faculty as the only organ for comprehending truth; that he
should not consider the voice of enraptured feeling, uncoordinated with
other forces of the spirit, as the faultless guide to truth; that he
should not consider the promptings of an isolated aesthetic sense,
independent of other faculties, as the true guide to the comprehension
of the supreme organisation of the universe; that he should not consider
even the dominant love of his heart, separate from the other demands of
the spirit, as the infallible guide to the attainment of the supreme
good; but that he should constantly seek in the depth of his soul that
inner root of understanding where all the separate faculties merge into
one living and whole vision of the mind [integral knowledge].
And, for the comprehension of truth in this union of all
spiritual faculties, the mind should not bring the thoughts present
before it to a sequence of separate judgments by each individual
faculty, attempting to coordinate their judgments into one common
meaning. But, when the whole vision of the mind is complete with every
movement of the soul, all its strivings should be heard in full accord,
blending into a single, harmonious sound.
The inner consciousness, which forms the common
life-forces in the depth of the soul for all the separate faculties of
reason, is hidden from the usual state of the human spirit, but is
accessible to the person who seeks it and is worthy of attaining the
highest truth. Such consciousness constantly elevates man’s very manner
of thought and, whilst humbling his rational conceit, does not constrain
the freedom of the natural laws of his reason. On the contrary, inner
consciousness strengthens his independence and, meanwhile, willingly
subordinates it to faith. Then he looks on all thinking emanating from
the highest source of rationality as incomplete and, therefore,
erroneous knowledge — knowledge which cannot serve as the expression of
the highest truth, although it might be useful in its subordinate
position and might sometimes even be a necessary step on the way to
other knowledge which stands at a still lower level.
That is why the free development of the natural laws of
reason cannot be harmful to the faith of the thinking Orthodox
Christian. He might be contaminated by unbelief, though only if his
external indigenous culture were inadequate. He could not arrive at
unbelief through the natural development of reason as thinking people of
other confessions have done. His basic notions about faith and reason
guard him against this misfortune. To him, faith is not a blind notion
which is in the state of
faithonly because it has not been developed by natural reason, and needs to be elevated by reason to the level of rationality and broken down into its constituent parts as evidence there is nothing specifically in it which cannot be found could not be found without the help of Divine Revelation in natural reason. Neither is faith an external authority alone, before which reason is compelled to become blind. It is, rather, an external and an inner authority simultaneously; the highest wisdom, life-giving for the mind. The development of natural reason serves faith only as a series of steps, and going beyond the usual state of the mind, faith thereby informs reason that it has departed from its original natural wholeness, and by this communication, instructs it to return to the level of higher activity. For the Orthodox believer knows the wholeness of truth needs the wholeness of reason, and the quest of this wholeness is his constant preoccupation.
In the presence of such a conviction, the entire chain
of the basic principles of natural reason [dianoia] which can serve as
the point of departure for all possible systems of thought is below the
reason of the believer [noesis], just as in external nature the whole
chain of organic life is below man, who is capable of an inner
consciousness of God and prayer at all levels of development. Standing
on this highest level of [noetic] thought, the Orthodox believer can
easily and harmlessly comprehend all systems of thought deriving from
the lower levels of reason; he can see their limitations and their
relative truthfulness. However, for the lower form of thought, the
higher is incomprehensible and appears nonsensical. Such, in general, is
the law of the human mind.
This independence of the basic thought of the Orthodox
believer from lower systems which might reach his mind is not the
exclusive possession of learned theologians, but is, so to speak, in the
very air of Orthodoxy. No matter how undeveloped the reasoning
faculties of the believer are, every Orthodox person is conscious in the
depths of his soul that Divine truth cannot be embraced by
considerations of ordinary reason and that it demands a higher spiritual
view acquired through inner existence, not through external erudition.
That is why he seeks true contemplation of God where he thinks he can
find a pure whole life which would assure him the wholeness of reason
and not where academic learning alone is exalted. That is why instances
are very rare of an Orthodox believer losing his faith solely as a
result of logical arguments capable of changing his rational concepts.
In most cases, he is enticed, rather than convinced, by unbelief. He
loses faith not because of intellectual difficulties, but because of the
temptations of life, and he brings in rationalistic considerations only
to justify the apostasy of his own heart to himself. Later, his
unbelief becomes fortified by some sort of rational system which
replaces his former faith, so that it then becomes difficult for him to
return to faith without first clearing the way for his reason. But, as
long as he believes with his heart, logical reasoning is harmless to
him. For him there is no thought separated from the memory of the inner
wholeness of the mind, of that point of concentration of
self-consciousness which is the true locus of supreme truth, and where
not abstract reasoning alone, but the sum total of man’s intellectual
and spiritual faculties stamps with one common imprint the credibility
of the thought which confronts reason — just as on Mount Athos each
monastery bears only one part of the seal which, when all its parts are
put together at the general council of the monastic representatives,
constitutes the one legal seal of the Holy Mountain.
Therefore, there are always two activities combined in
the thinking of the Orthodox believer. Following the development of his
own understanding, he meantime follows the very manner of his thinking,
constantly striving to elevate reason to the level at which it can be in
sympathy with faith. Inner consciousness, or sometimes only a vague
awareness of this ultimate limit which is being sought, is present in
every exertion of his reason, in every
breathof his thought; and if, at any time, the development of an original culture in the world of the Orthodox believer is possible, it is thus obvious that this peculiarity of Orthodox thought deriving from the special relationship of reason to faith must determine its predominant orientation. Only such thought could, in time, liberate the intellectual life of the Orthodox world from the distorting influences of alien culture and also from the suffocating oppression of ignorance, both equally odious to Orthodox culture. For the development of thought giving a particular meaning to all intellectual life, or, even better, the development of philosophy, is determined by the union of the two opposite ends of human thought, the one wedded to the highest questions of faith and the one where philosophy touches on the development of the sciences and external culture.
Philosophy is neither one of the sciences nor faith. It
is both the sum total and the common basis of all sciences and is the
conductor of thought between them and faith. Where there is faith but no
development of rational learning, philosophy cannot exist. Where
science and learning have developed but there is no faith or where faith
has disappeared, philosophical convictions replace convictions of faith
and, appearing in the form of prejudice, give direction to the thought
and life of a people. Not all who share philosophical convictions have
studied the systems from which they derive, but all accept the final
conclusions of these systems, so to speak, on faith that others are
correct in their convictions. Resting on these mental prejudices on the
one hand, and stimulated by the problems of contemporary learning on the
other, human reason gives birth to new philosophical systems
corresponding to the mutual relationship between established prejudices
and contemporary culture.
But where the faith of a people has one meaning and one
orientation whilst the learning borrowed from another people has a
different meaning and different orientation, one of two things must
happen: learning will force out faith, giving rise to appropriate
philosophical convictions, or faith, overcoming this external learning
in the thinking consciousness of the people, will produce its own
philosophy from contact with it, which will give a different meaning to
external learning and will endow it with a different dominant principle.
The latter occurred when Christianity appeared in the
midst of pagan culture. Not only science, but pagan philosophy was
transformed into an instrument of Christian culture and was incorporated
into the body of Christian philosophy as a subordinate principle.
As long as external culture continued to exist in the
East, Orthodox Christian philosophy flourished. It was extinguished when
freedom died in Greece and Greek culture was destroyed. But traces have
been preserved in the writings of the Holy Fathers like living sparks
ready to flare up at first contact with believing thought and again to
ignite the guiding beacon for reason in search of truth.
Yet, restoring the philosophy of the Holy Fathers as it
was in their time is impossible. Having grown out of the relationship of
faith to their contemporary culture, it had to correspond to the
problems of its own time and to the culture in which it developed.
Development of new aspects of systematic and social learning also
demands a corresponding new development of philosophy. But the truths
expressed in the speculative writings of the Holy Fathers could serve
the development of philosophy as a life-bearing embryo and a bright
guiding light.
To counterpoise these precious and life-giving truths to
the contemporary state of philosophy; to become imbued with their
meaning as much as possible; to consider all questions of contemporary
culture in relation to them, all logical truths acquired by science, all
the fruits of the millennial experiences of reason acquired in its
diverse activities; to derive general conclusions from all these
considerations corresponding to the present demands of culture — here is
a problem whose solution could change the whole orientation of the
culture of a people where the beliefs of the Orthodox faith are in
disagreement with a borrowed culture.
The satisfactory solution of this great problem demands
the concerted action of like-minded people. A philosophy which does not
wish to remain purely academic and without influence, and which must
become living conviction, must also develop from the living interaction
of convictions striving for the same goal in various ways but with unity
of purpose. For everything essential in man’s soul is the result of
social forces. Personal conviction must then encounter the problems of
surrounding culture not in theory but in reality. For only out of real
relationships with reality are thoughts kindled which illuminate the
mind and warm the heart.
Even so, in order that we may understand the
relationship which the philosophy of the ancient Church Fathers might
have to contemporary culture, it is not enough to apply it to the
requirements of our time. It is necessary to keep constantly in mind its
connection to its contemporary culture to it in order to be able to
distinguish what is essential in it from what is only passing and
relative. At that time, the extent of the development of science and the
character of its development were not the same as they are today, and
the things that agitated and disturbed man’s heart were not the same as
those that agitate and disturb man today.
The ancient world found itself in an irreconcilable
contradiction with Christianity, not only when Christianity was
struggling with polytheism, but even when the state called itself
Christian. The world and the Church were two opposite extremes which in
essence were mutually exclusive, although outwardly they tolerated each
other. Paganism was not destroyed with the coming of monotheism. It
flourished in the structure of the state; in the laws; in the selfish,
callous, coercive, and cunning Roman government, among officials
insolently venal and openly deceitful; in the law courts, which were
manifestly corrupt and capable of disguising flagrant injustice as
formal legality; in the mores of the people, immersed in venality and
luxury; in the Roman customs and games — in a word, in the sum total of
the social relations of the Empire. Constantine the Great recognised the
government as Christian, but he was not able to reform it in the
Christian spirit. Although physical martyrdom ended, moral martyrdom
remained. The legal and public recognition of Christian truth was a
great achievement, but the embodiment of this truth in the structure of
the state required time. If Constantine’s heirs had been pervaded by the
same sincere respect for the Church, the East Roman Empire might
perhaps have become Christian. Instead, its rulers were for the most
part heretics or apostates who oppressed the Church under the guise of
protection, using it only as an instrument of their own power.
Meanwhile, the very composition of the Roman Empire was
such that it was hardly possible for its governing authority to renounce
its pagan character. Rome represented a state authority in an abstract
form. Below the government there were no people whose expression it
might have been, with whom it could have been in sympathetic relations
for the better development of the state’s life. The Roman government
constituted the external and oppressive link between many different
nationalities who were alien to one another in language and,
additionally, whose interests conflicted. The strength of the government
rested on the equilibrium of national animosities. The people were held
together by force, but they were not united. Every expression of public
and local spirit which is the food and sustenance of public morality,
was repugnant to the government. The various peoples had their native
countries, but the common fatherland had disappeared and could not have
been restored except through inner unanimity of thought.
The Christian Church alone remained as the inner, living
bond among the people. Only love for the heavenly kingdom united them.
Only unanimity of thought in faith led them to a living mutual sympathy.
Only unity of inner convictions firmly established in their minds could
have led them in time to a better life on earth. This is why the
longing for unanimity of thought and spirit in the Church constituted
the full expression of the love of God, love of humanity, love of the
fatherland, and love of truth. Between the citizen of Rome and the son
of the Church, there was nothing in common. Only one possibility for
social action remained open to the Christian, and that consisted of
complete and unconditional protest against the world. The East Roman
Christian could save his inner convictions only by sacrificing his
public life. He achieved this by accepting martyrdom and by fleeing into
the desert, by shutting himself up in the monastery. The desert and the
monastery were, one might say, almost the sole area for the Christian
moral and intellectual development of man. For Christianity, instead of
avoiding intellectual development, incorporated it into itself.
As a result of this state of affairs, problems of the
cultural life of the time could not be of social character; hence
philosophy had to limit itself to the development of the inner
contemplative life. Similarly, it could not embrace an interest in
history, which rests on an interest in public matters. Moral issues
affected philosophy only to the extent to which they were related to the
inner life of the isolated individual. It was almost oblivious to man’s
external life and the laws of development of family, civic, public, and
state relations. Although the general principles of these relations are
to be found in the general philosophical concepts of man, they did not
lead to systematic conclusions. Perhaps general moral concepts — the
less interference there was by transitory, worldly influences in
monastic life — were the more purely and profoundly revealed in the
isolated intellectual life of the monasteries. But the inner purity and
depth did not have that completeness of external development which
another epoch and another state of external culture would have demanded
of them.
In the questions of the inner contemplative life of
those times, however, and in the problems of the socio-philosophic
culture of our day, there is a common element: human reason. The nature
of reason, considered from the eminence of a profound theology
experienced in the highest development of inner, spiritual
contemplation, manifests itself in an appearance entirely different from
which it presents itself when limited by the development of external
everyday life. Of course, its general laws are the same. But when reason
is elevated to its highest level of development, it displays the new
aspects and new faculties of its nature which shed new light on its
general laws as well.
The concept of reason which has been elaborated in
recent philosophy, and whose expression is to be found in the
Schellingian-Hegelian system, would not unconditionally contradict the
concept of reason which we notice in the works of the Holy Fathers if
only it did not present itself as the highest instrument of cognition,
and if, as a result of this pretension to the highest power of
cognition, it did not limit truth to that aspect of cognition which is
accessible only to this abstractly rational manner of thinking
[dianoetic].
All false deductions of rational thought result from its
pretension to the highest, complete cognition of truth. If it
recognised its limitations and saw itself as one of the tools for
cognition of truth — and not as the only one — it would present its
deductions as provisional and referent solely to its limited point of
view; it would anticipate other, supreme, and most truthful deductions
from another, supreme and most truthful manner of thinking. Rational
thought is accepted in this sense by the thinking Christian who,
rejecting its ultimate results, can with greater benefit to his mental
development examine its relative truth and accept as the lawful
achievement of reason everything that is true and enlightening in the
development of its speculations, however one-sided.
If, however, philosophical reason realised its
limitations, it would, through its development within these limitations,
adopt another orientation capable of leading it to fuller knowledge.
But, awareness of its limitations would mark the death of its absolute
authority. That is why it has always feared this realisation, the more
so as it has always been close to it. It constantly altered its forms in
order to avoid it. No sooner would its inadequacy be understood than it
would evade this misunderstanding by mainfesting itself in another
appearance, leaving its earlier form as a mere empty shell in the hands
of its adversaries. Thus, in order to avoid charges of inadequacy, it
passed from formal-logic proofs to experiential observations on the one
hand, and to the inner consciousness of truth on the other, and called
its earlier manner of thought dry and rationalistic, and its later — rational.
But, having also discovered the inadequacy of the new form in the
course of its development, philosophical reason referred to it also as
dry and rationalistic and proceeded to pure reason. When Jacobi
excoriated the narrowness of the theory of pure reason as expressed in
the systems of Kant and Fichte, he learnt to his surprise at the end of
his lengthy polemics, extending over many years, that everything he had
said about reason should be applied to the understanding. The
theory of Kant and Fichte proved to be rationalistic. The development of
reason was to begin only with the system of Schelling and Hegel. In
1802, pointing to Schelling’s system, Hegel wrote,
Only now could, strictly speaking, the philosophy of reason begin, for the cycle of development of rationalistic understanding came to an end with Fichte’s system.
Thus, reason, as understood by most recent philosophy,
does not wish to be confused with logical understanding contained in the
formal concatenation of concepts and impelled by syllogistic deductions
and proofs. According to the laws of intellectual necessity, reason in
its latest manifestation derives its knowledge not from abstract
notions, but from the very root of self-consciousness, where existence
and thought are united into one absolute identity. Its thinking process
consists not of logical development set in motion by abstract
speculations, but of dialectical development deriving from the very
essence of the subject. The object of thought, confronting the mind’s
eye, transforms itself from form to form, from concept to concept,
constantly acquiring a more nearly complete meaning. And as the mind
concentrates on the subject of its thought, it discovers in it an inner
contradiction destroying its former concept. This contradictory,
negative concept confronting the mind also reveals its bankruptcy and
discovers in itself the necessity of a positive foundation latent in it,
which now appears as the union of the positive and negative categories
into a single complex (the concrete). But this new concept in
turn scarcely appears to the mind as the final result of understanding,
when, in this pretension to ultimate independence, it now reveals its
inadequacy and displays its negative side. This negative side once again
brings out its positive, which is again subjected to the same
transforming process until the whole cycle of the dialectical
development of thought is completed, progressing from the initial
principle of consciousness towards a general and pure abstraction of
thought, which constitutes at the same time general essentiality. Then,
by the same dialectical process, consciousness is given full content by
the entire development of being and thought, [which are understood] as
the identical phenomenon of a realised rationality and self-conscious
essentiality.
But, having said its last word, philosophical reason at
the same time furnished the mind with an opportunity to realise its
limitations. The same dialectical process which had served reason in the
construction of its philosophy was subjected to the same disintegrative
assumptions, whereupon it showed itself to rational consciousness as
solely the negative aspect of knowledge, comprising possible truth only,
not actual truth, and standing in need of another form of thinking —
which would be the positively known, not the hypothetically known, and
which would stand above logical self-development just as the really
occurring stands above the merely potential.
This consciousness of the limitations and the
unsatisfactory character of the latest expression of philosophical
thought now constitutes the highest stage of the intellectual
development of the West. This is not the opinion of dilettantes in
philosophy, not the outcries of people attacking philosophy from some
tangential motivation; it is not even the judgment of people like Krause
and Baader, who with their penetrating philosophical thought did much
to help in the development of recent philosophy, but who did not command
sufficient authority over men’s minds for their protest against its
absolute truthfulness to be able to change the direction of
philosophical development — they acted powerfully in another field which
lies unseen between science and life, but none of them founded a
special school of philosophy.1 The one-sidedness and
unsatisfactory nature of rational thinking, and of most recent
philosophy, as its fullest manifestations, were recognised and expressed
with obvious and irrefutable clarity by the same great thinker
[Schelling] who was first to create the latest philosophy and to
elevate, according to Hegel’s confession, rational thought from formal
calculation to essential rationality.
For the latest German philosophy is attributable to
Schelling as much as to Hegel. It was begun by Schelling and was
confirmed in its new foundation and developed in many of its separate
elements by him, and he shared with Hegel the introduction of it into
the general consciousness of Germany. Hegel, who was long reckoned a
pupil and follower of Schelling, is responsible for the more detailed
development of recent philosophy that embraces all branches of science
and represents the completion of a system founded on an allegedly
scientific basis. Schelling could the more clearly recognise the
limitations of this philosophy because it was his own thought.2
Schelling’s authority and, even more, the obvious
justice of his views with respect to the limitations of rationality,
visibly shook the absolute confidence in the deductions of most recent
philosophy in Germany and was one of the factors which accounted for the
growing indifference to philosophy. Of course, there are still
Hegelians, and they will exist for a long time, for the whole character
of contemporary culture is in tune with their orientation. But when
thought, at the very peak of its development, has acknowledged its
inadequacy, a new orientation is possible. The majority making up the
crowd may, for a long time, continue to hold obsolete views, but the
conviction of the crowd cannot restore the earlier spark of confidence.
The celebrated Erdmann calls himself the “last Mohican” among Hegel’s
pupils. New celebrities in the field of philosophy are no longer to be
seen, and they are hardly possible any longer.
But Schelling’s last system could not yet have an
influence on men’s minds, because it combines in itself two antithetical
aspects, one of which is almost certainly true, while the other is
almost certainly false. The first, the negative, shows the inadequacy of
rationality; the second, the positive, presents the structure of a new
system. But these two aspects lack essential cohesion; they may be
separated from each other, and perforce will be separated. Then the
negative influence of Schelling’s thought will be incomparably stronger.
Once he was convinced of the limitation of autonomous thought, and of
the necessity of Divine Revelation preserved in tradition, and
simultaneously of the necessity of living faith as the supreme
rationality and as the essential element of cognition, Schelling did not
deliberately turn to Christianity, but came to it naturally through the
profound and correct development of his rational self-consciousness.
For the possibility of the consciousness of man’s basic relationship to
God lies in the very core of human reason, and in its very nature. Man’s
thoughts may hover in abstract oblivion of its basic relationships only
if it has broken away from this vital profundity or if it has failed to
reach it. By virtue of his innate genius and the extradordinary
development of his profound philosophical thought, Schelling is one of
those beings who are born not once in centuries, but once in millennia.
But, in his search for Divine Revelation, where could he
find its pure expression corresponding to his rational need for faith? A
Protestant from birth, Schelling was, nevertheless, so sincere and
conscientious in his inner convictions he could not fail to see the
inadequacies of Protestantism, which rejected the tradition preserved in
the Latin confession. He often expressed this view, with the result
that, for a long time, rumours were rampant in Germany that he had gone
over to the Latins. But he also clearly saw in the Latin confession the
confusion of true and untrue tradition, of the Divine and the human.
Heavy must be the lot of the man who languishes in the
grip of an inner thirst for Divine Truth, and who cannot find the pure
religion which can satisfy this all-pervasive need. He has only one
alternative: to seek out and obtain with his own powers from the
confused Christian tradition whatever corresponds to his inner notion of
Christian truth. A lamentable task — creating a faith for oneself!
Here, Schelling was guided not by speculative
considerations alone, whose inadequacy he so clearly recognised. In
addition to [studying] the Holy Scriptures, he sought support for his
thought in the actual consciousness of God of all mankind, to the extent
to which it preserved the tradition of the pristine Divine Revelation
to man. In the mythology of ancient peoples can be found traces of a
Revelation which, although distorted, had not been lost. The fundamental
relationship of early man to God appeared in every nation in a
peculiar, circumscribed form as humanity became divided into different
groups in accordance with the branching out of the various peoples. This
peculiar form of God-consciousness determined the very character of a
people. But, inside all these more or less distorting limitations, there
remained the unchangeable, permanent features of the general essential
nature of Revelation. The agreement between these general inner, basic
principles of each mythology, and the basic principles of Christian
tradition, expressed for Schelling the pure truth of Divine Revelation.
Such a view of the history of human beliefs could be an
extremely rich source from which Christian thought might draw, if the
preliminary stages of that thought already rested on a firm foundation.
But the vagueness of the preliminary conviction and the vagueness of the
inner meaning of mythology, subject to the more or less arbitrary
interpretation of the investigator, were the reasons why Schelling’s
Christian philosophy was neither Christian nor philosophy. It differed
from Christianity in its most fundamental dogmas, and from philosophy by
the very manner of cognition.
Moreover, whilst asserting actual truth based not on
abstract speculation, but on thought imbued with faith, Schelling paid
no attention to that special character of the inner activity of reason
which constitutes the essential attribute of believing thought. For the
form of rational activity changes in accordance with the level to which
reason is elevated. Although reason is one, and its nature is one, its
forms of action are different, just as its deductions are different
depending on the level on which it finds itself, and on the force which
impels it and guides it. For this impelling and animating force derives
not from thought confronting reason, but arises from the very inner
condition of reason and moves towards thought, in which this force finds
its rest and through which it is communicated to other rational beings.
This inner nature of reason ordinarily escapes the
attention of Western thinkers. Being accustomed to abstract logical
thinking where all knowledge depends on the formal development of the
object of thought and where the whole meaning is absorbed by that
inexpressible aspect of thought, they do not pay attention to the
faculty of the soul which transcends the formal nature of logical
concatenations, and which accomplishes the movement of thought and
constantly accompanies it, being suspended, so to speak, above the
expression of thought and communicating to it meaning incompatible with
external definition and results independent of external form. Hence,
Schelling sought the expression of religious dogmas in the writings of
the Holy Fathers, but did not appreciate their speculative concepts of
reason and the laws of higher cognition. Hence, the positive side of his
system, lacking the inner character of believing thought, found little
sympathy in Germany and finds even less in Russia. Russia might be
enticed by the logical systems of alien philosophies which are still new
for her, but with respect to the philosophy of the believer she is
stricter than other European countries, having lofty examples of
religious thought in the ancient Holy Fathers and in the great sacred
writings of all times, not excluding the present. On the other hand, the
negative aspect of Schelling’s system, embracing the inadequacy of
rational thought, could scarcely be so impartially appraised in Germany,
which is accustomed to its abstract and logical thought pattern, as in
Russia where, after the initial youthful enthusiasm over an alien
system, the Russian can return more easily to essential rationality,
particularly when this essential rationality is consonant with his
historical uniqueness.
Therefore, I believe German philosophy, in combination
with the development which it received in Schelling’s last system, could
serve us as the most convenient point of departure on our way from
borrowed systems to an independent philosophy corresponding to the basic
principles of ancient Russia culture and be capable of subjecting the
divided culture of the West to the integrated consciousness of believing
reason.
Notes
- Holibeus [Chalybäus] cannot be included in the category of philosophers opposed to the latest orientation of philosophy. For, although his principles are basically somewhat at variance with Hegel's view of the general laws of reason, these differences do not remove him from the sphere of rational, abstract thinking. Görres, who was one of the most celebrated followers of Schelling, and who went over from philosophy to faith, also could not exert any influence on the general development of the mind because his transition was accomplished not as a result of the correct development of consciousness, but as a result of his personal peculiarity and of extraneous influences.
- In his history of philosophy, Hegel indicates several differences between his system and Schelling's, but these differences belong to that period of Schelling’s philosophy when his thought had already begun to take another direction – which, incidentally, Hegel himself mentions. The only difference between Schelling’s first system and Hegel’s system is to be found in the method by which the basic thought is expounded. That inner contradiction of thought which Schelling presents in the combined manifestation of the two polarities and of their identity appears in Hegel in the consecutive movement of consciousness from one definition of thought to its antithesis. With respect to intellectual intuition of which Schelling spoke and which was not encompassed by Hegel's system, it may be said that it had no essential significance in Schelling’s first system either. Schelling mentions it, but he does not develop it. This was only a harbinger of the future direction of his thought.
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário